MAN AND LOGOS: HERACLITUS’ SECRET
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.15802/ampr.v0i17.206726Keywords:
Heraclitus, Logos, immortality, soul, self-knowledge, divinity, anthropology, meaning of life, memoryAbstract
Purpose. The author believes that the main topic of philosophical studies of Heraclitus was not nature, not dialectics, and not political philosophy; he was engaged in the development of philosophical anthropology, and all other questions raised by him were subordinated to it to one degree or another. It is anthropology that is the most "dark" part of the teachings of this philosopher, therefore the purpose of this article is to identify the hidden anthropological message of Heraclitus. In case of success, it will become clear what made him "darken". Theoretical basis. The methodological basis of the article is the anthropological understanding of fragments of Heraclitus’ texts presented in a historical and philosophical context. Originality. The philosophical concept of Heraclitus is still a mystery for researchers of his work. The author of the article proposed such a variant of interpretation, within the framework of which different elements of this concept fit into a consistent model. Conclusions. The article proves that although the anthropological turn in philosophy is traditionally associated with the activities of the sophists and Socrates, the previous philosophical thought was also not devoid of anthropological ideas. Moreover, pre-Socratic philosophers posed problems, the interpretation of which brought the doctrine of man to the level of high-order abstractions, while surprisingly preserving the concreteness of the life-meaning questions that confront him. And one of the brightest representatives of pre-Socratic anthropology was Heraclitus of Ephesus. Religion was the motivator that made him study the world, man, and society. The doctrine of the Logos developed by Heraclitus had a tremendous impact on Plato and Philo of Alexandria, and through them on the author of the Fourth Gospel, who begins his story with a "Greek" rethinking of the mystery of the Incarnation. If Heraclitus claimed that a person carries a particle of the Logos, then John (or the one who wrote on his behalf) proclaimed that the Logos itself incorporated a particle of man. Despite all the differences between these approaches, each of them postulated the cosmic (divine) significance of human existence, which means that it brought anthropology to the ontological level.References
Adomenas, M. (1999). Heraclitus on Religion. Phronesis, 44(2), 87-113. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1163/156852899321331752 (in English)
Bazaluk, O. (2019). The Revival of the Notion of Arete in Contemporary Philosophy. Schole, 13(1), 198-207.
Betegh, G. (2006). The Derveni Papyrus: Cosmology, Theology and Interpretation. New York: Cambridge University Press. (in English)
Brann, E. T. H. (2011). The Logos of Heraclitus: The First Philosopher of the West on its Most Interesting Term. Philadelphia, PA: Paul Dry Books. (in English)
Christidis, T. (2012). Heraclitus and Parmenides, Philosophers of Becoming and Being. Philosophical Inquiry, 36(1-2), 18-41. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5840/philinquiry2012361/23 (in English)
Cicero. (1967). On the Nature of the Gods. Academics. H. Rackham, Trans. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (in English)
Diogenes Laertius. (1925). Books 6-10. In Lives of Eminent Philosophers (Vol. 2). R. D. Hicks, Trans. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (in English)
Habash, J. (2019). Heraclitus and the Riddle of Nature. Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy, 23(2), 275-286. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5840/epoche2019214133 (in English)
Halapsis, A. V. (2019). Gods of Transhumanism. Anthropological Measurements of Philosophical Research, 16, 78-90. DOI: https://doi.org/10.15802/ampr.v0i16.188397 (in English)
Johnstone, M. A. (2014). On 'Logos' in Heraclitus. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 47, 1-29. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198722717.003.0001 (in English)
Kouremenos, T., Parássoglou, G. M., & Tsantsanoglou, K. (Eds.). (2006). The Derveni Papyrus. Firenze: Leo S. Olschki. (in English)
Laks, A., & Most, G. W. (Eds.). (1997). Studies on the Derveni Papyrus. Oxford: Clarendon Press. (in English)
Lumpkin, J. B. (2010). The Books of Enoch: A Complete Volume. Blountsville, AL: Fifth Estate. (in English)
Martínez, F. G., & Tigchelaar, E. J. C. (Eds.). (1999). The Dead Sea Scrolls Study Edition. Leiden: Brill. (in English)
McKirahan, R. D. (2010). Philosophy Before Socrates: An Introduction with Texts and Commentary (2nd ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett. (in English)
Narecki, K. (2012). The Image of the River in the Fragments of Heraclitus. Philotheos, 12, 66-77. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5840/philotheos2012126 (in English)
Neels, R. (2018). Elements and Opposites in Heraclitus. Apeiron, 51(4), 427-452. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/apeiron-2017-0029 (in English)
Plato. (1997). Complete Works. J. M. Cooper & D. S. Hutchinson (Eds.). Indianapolis: Hackett. (in English)
Popper, K. R. (1945). The Spell of Plato. In The Open Society and Its Enemies (Vol. 1). London: Routledge. (in English)
Reames, R. (2013). The Logos Paradox: Heraclitus, Material Language, and Rhetoric. Philosophy & Rhetoric, 46(3), 328-350. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5325/philrhet.46.3.0328 (in English)
Robitzsch, J. M. (2018). Heraclitus’ Political Thought. Apeiron, 51(4), 405-426. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/apeiron-2017-0009 (in English)
Schur, D. M. (1994). The Way of Oblivion: Heraclitus and Kafka. Harvard University. (in English)
Shaw, D. (2018). On Misunderstanding Heraclitus: the Justice of Organisation Structure. Philosophy of Management, 18(2), 157-167. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40926-018-0097-y (in English)
Sider, D. (1997). Heraclitus in the Derveni Papyrus. In A. Laks & G. W. Most (Eds.), Studies on the Derveni Papyrus (pp. 129-148). Oxford: Clarendon Press. (in English)
Vieira, C. (2013). Heraclitus’ Bow Composition. Classical Quarterly, 63(2), 473-490. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/s0009838813000037 (in English)
Published
How to Cite
Issue
Section
License
Copyright (c) 2020 Anthropological Measurements of Philosophical Research
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
- Authors retain copyright and grant the journal right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution License that allows others to share the work with an acknowledgement of the work's authorship and initial publication in this journal.
- Authors are able to enter into separate, additional contractual arrangements for the non-exclusive distribution of the journal's published version of the work (e.g., post it to an institutional repository or publish it in a book), with an acknowledgement of its initial publication in this journal.
- Authors are permitted and encouraged to post their work online (e.g., in institutional repositories or on their website) prior to and during the submission process, as it can lead to productive exchanges, as well as earlier and greater citation of published work (See The Effect of Open Access).